“Against boredom even gods struggle in vain.” – Friedrich
Nietzsche
Boredom in all its facets is inherent to us. Being bored never
escapes our being. However we are paranoid of the very experience of being
bored. Feeling depraves us of pleasure of being. Boredom invariably relates to
work as its polarity. Proximity of the word 'boredom' being appeared (somewhere
during 1852) during the industrial age, which betrays it's relation to work and
being industrious. But, immediately one can sense a paradox on how when
humanity was turning towards its most industriously occupied time does the word
for being bored come to be. Moreover the relationship between boredom and work
goes deeper than this. To understand it more from philosophical and theological
perspective let us turn to Nietzsche, Kierkegaard and Heidegger for their
insights.
For Nietzsche boredom can be experienced as
a resultant of work without pleasure.[1]
This essential relationship between work and pleasure is almost totally negated
in work ethics of Christianity. The divorcing of work and pleasure begins in
Christianity with the advent of monasticism. Solitary lives of the monks
naturally lead to what the early fathers of the church called "acedia" (sloth). In order to combat
acedia, monasteries were formed and the "rule and life" (regula et vita) for the monks were
created wherein everything was regulated according to specific time (horologium). Lives of the monks were so
meticulously organized so as to evade all possibility of acedia or boredom. In
this meticulousness and horologium
vitae of the monks work is allegorized as spiritual work. In Agamben's study of
monasticism he writes, "The spiritualization of the work of the hands that
is accomplished in this way can be seen as a significant precursor of the
Protestant ascesis of labor …"[2]
Thus monasticism brings into Christian work ethics a form of asceticism,
wherein the work is not done for the sake of pleasure itself but to engage the
time by avoiding boredom. This explains the paranoia of boredom among us.
Within the same lines Max Weber when analysing Protestantism (especially
Calvinism) and their work ethics writes, "the summum bonum of this ethic,
the earning of more and more money, combined with the strict avoidance of all
spontaneous enjoyment of life"[3]
which he calls "Worldly asceticism of this form of Protestantism." In
contrary to this Nietzsche writes, "Now there are rare individuals who
would rather perish than work without taking pleasure in their work … they do
not fear boredom as much as work without pleasure."[4]
Boredom is the "lull of the soul" and one has to completely let it
take him over until its effect leads to something creative.
In talking about boredom Kierkegaard has
even more interesting analysis. He declares "All human beings, then, are
boring,"[5]
further he distinguishes two types of boring people, those who bore others who
are called as "plebians" and those who bore themselves are called as
"the nobility." And within this distinction the plebians are the most
boring because, "those who do not bore themselves are busy in the world in
one way or another, but for that very reason they are, of all people, the most
boring of all, the most unbearable." And it is the nobility as in the
Nietzschean analysis are the people who are work for pleasure and will avoid
all work without pleasure, unlike the plebians who work all the time without
pleasure, is the most boring. Plebians, "in the fact that the busiest
workers of all, those whirring insects with their bustling buzzing, are the
most boring of all, and if they are not bored, it is because they do not know
what boredom is." And those who know boredom are "an immediate
genius." And using boredom as genius, Kierkegaard advises all those who
are bored to "limit" themselves. This limiting can help in one become
more creative. He explains this "principle of limitation" as
"The more a person limits himself, the more resourceful he becomes."
This principle he explains in a more playful way by giving an example,
"Think of our school days; we were at an age when there was no esthetic
consideration in the choosing of our teachers, and therefore they were often
very boring-how resourceful we were then. What fun we had catching a fly,
keeping it prisoner under a nutshell, and watching it run around with it! What
delight in cutting a hole in the desk, confining a fly in it, and peeking at it
through a piece of paper!"[6]
This advice is as nostalgic as it gets for us from Kierkegaard.
In Fundamental
Concepts of Metaphysics, Martin Heidegger gives us a more serious analysis
of boredom. He identifies three types of boredom,[7]
'Becoming Bored by Something', 'Being Bore with Something' and 'Profound
Boredom.' In the first type we experience boredom from situation we are forced
to be in, example waiting for the train in a deserted railway station. This
boredom arises as a result of "being left empty." Second type of
boredom is not the result of the things or the sense of being left empty but we
bore ourselves or in other words, "what is boring can bore us without
directly coming toward us from particular boring things", for example the
feeling of retrospective boringness that could occur to us even after the most
lively event. In the second type boring is actually "self-forming
emptiness." The profound boredom is what Heidegger views as essential
boredom, a condition of dasein (being) in the contemporary age. This profound
boredom is unlike the first and second type of boredom; herein boredom is
"not this or that being that we are bored by. It is not we who, on the
occasion of this particular situation, are ourselves bored - rather. It is
boring for one." In this boredom it is "the self, one's own beloved
ego of which we say that I myself, you yourself, we ourselves are
bored." It is to this profoundness of the Heidegger calls our attention
to. The characteristic of the profound boredom is the sense of indifference.
The indifference is that which drives the being out of every shelter of work
and leaves no shadow to hide, we are made to confront our own existence as the
profound indifference itself. It is to this indifference, that we need "to
listen to what it has to tell us." This telling does not lead to
"despair" but rather to the "possibilities of Dasein."[8]
Therefore in Heidegger's view the superficial boredom that appears through the
objects can be warded off through some work without pleasure, whereas the
profound boredom leaves no room for escape rather, lights up everything and
leaves the bare bones of our existence or our being (dasein) in stark light for
us which is stripping at first but later leads to the achievement of
possibilities of dasein.
[1]
Cf. “Work and Boredom,” Friedrich Nietzsche, The Gay Science (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2001), 57-58.
Agamben, Giorgio, and Adam Kotsko. The highest poverty: Monastic rules and
form-of-life. Meridian : crossing aesthetics. California: Stanford
University Press, 2013.
Heidegger, Martin. The fundamental concepts of metaphysics: World, finitude, solitude.
Studies in Continental thought. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1995.
Kierkegaard, Søren, Howard V. Hong, and Edna
H. Hong. Either/or. Kierkegaard's
writings. 3-4. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1987.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. The Gay Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001.
Weber, Max. The Protestant ethic and the spirit of capitalism. Routledge
classics. London, New York: Routledge, 2001.